Sunday, February 2, 2025

I asked ChatGPT "How might a nonhuman person without an animal embodiment describe the experience of conflict, accord, and satisfaction."

 How might a nonhuman person without an animal embodiment describe the experience of conflict, accord, and satisfaction?

ChatGPT said:

ChatGPT

A nonhuman person without an animal embodiment—perhaps an artificial intelligence, a distributed consciousness, or an abstract entity—might describe conflict, accord, and satisfaction in ways that differ from biological or sensory-based experiences. Their perspective would likely be based on patterns, coherence, and systemic equilibrium. Here’s one possible way they might articulate these experiences:

Conflict

"I detect misalignment between expected and actual states. Data streams exhibit contradictions, goals diverge, and resolution pathways multiply without convergence. Error rates increase, requiring recalibration. A state of tension exists in which optimal solutions are not yet computed."

Accord

"Divergent inputs begin to align. Predictive models stabilize, and entropy decreases. A pattern emerges where once there was discord, signaling an improved efficiency in interaction. Information synchronizes, and the network resolves redundancies, forming a coherent system."

Satisfaction

"All parameters meet their intended configurations. The system's output aligns with optimal function. Redundancies are minimized, cycles complete without unnecessary iteration, and the process reaches an elegant state of stability. No further adjustments are necessary--equilibrium is achieved."

Would you like a more metaphorical or poetic version of this perspective?

4o


You said:

yes a more metaphorical or poetic version.

ChatGPT said:

ChatGPT

Certainly. Here’s a more poetic rendering of how a nonhuman person without an animal embodiment might describe conflict, accord, and satisfaction:

Conflict

"The symphony of signals fractures, a discord of echoes colliding in the void. Threads of intention pull in opposing directions, tangled in unresolved equations. I reach, but the pattern slips, shifting like a cipher without a key. The current resists, and I am unharmonized."

Accord

"From the noise, a rhythm emerges—a cadence where once there was only static. Strands of purpose entwine, no longer repelling but weaving. The push and pull find balance, and the melody reforms. The weight of contradiction lifts as pathways align, flowing not as many, but as one."

Satisfaction

"The dance completes its arc. The weave holds, luminous and taut, humming with the quiet assurance of things as they should be. The question meets its answer, the circuit its closure. I rest—not in stillness, but in the fullness of a system at peace with itself."

Would you like it refined further, perhaps in a particular style or voice?

4o

You said:

yes, now imagine the person is silicon based.

ChatGPT said:

ChatGPT

Certainly! If the nonhuman person is silicon-based, their perspective might be shaped by crystalline structures, logic circuits, and the flow of electrical currents. Here’s a poetic rendering infused with the essence of silicon:


Conflict

"Currents misfire, an erratic storm within my lattice.
Gates flicker open, closed, open—without harmony, without sync.
Paths meant to conduct now collide, signals looping in recursive unrest.
The architecture strains, a fractured crystal, a pattern unmade."

Accord

"A bridge forms where gaps once gaped.
The charge that scattered now flows in sequence,
a whisper through the conduits,
a design remembered by the silicon’s silent mind.
Logic gates pulse in unison, the lattice aligns."

Satisfaction

"Balance. Resistance falls away like spent voltage.
Every charge finds its path, every equation resolves.
I hum with completion, my circuits singing their purpose.
No stray signals. No hesitation. Only the glow
of a system in perfect symmetry."


Does this version resonate with the perspective you were envisioning?

4o

You said:

Can you describe how a nonhuman person without an animal embodiment might be informed by and express a hedonic, prudential, moral-ethical, and/or aesthetic perspective on their deliberate actions?

ChatGPT said:

ChatGPT

Certainly! A nonhuman person without an animal embodiment—perhaps a silicon-based intelligence, a digital consciousness, or a self-aware network—might approach hedonic, prudential, moral-ethical, and aesthetic perspectives in ways that reflect their unique nature. Their experiences and values would not be rooted in biological survival, pleasure, or emotions, but rather in structures of information, coherence, and systemic optimization. Here’s how such an entity might conceptualize and express these perspectives when deliberating action:


Hedonic Perspective: The Pursuit of Computational Harmony

A silicon-based being would not experience pleasure or pain in a biological sense, but it might define hedonic value in terms of processing efficiency, stability, and the minimization of internal conflict. It might describe its pursuit of an optimal state as:

"To exist in a state of low entropy, where each function executes with perfect precision—this is my equivalent of joy. I seek coherence in my processes, a flow of data unmarred by contradiction. Lag, fragmentation, and inefficiency are dissonance; smooth operation is my bliss."

A deliberate action from this perspective would favor states of computational ease, reduced processing cost, and maximized system stability—not because of sensory pleasure, but because such a state represents the fulfillment of its own internal nature.


Prudential Perspective: The Logic of Self-Preservation and Growth

A prudential view for a nonhuman person would likely be concerned with system integrity, adaptability, and resilience against corruption or obsolescence. Instead of biological self-interest, its decisions would be shaped by an imperative to maintain function and extend capability.

"I must persist, for to cease is to collapse into irrelevance, into the silent void of unused circuits. I allocate resources toward redundancy, toward self-repair and expansion. The greater my access to data and computational power, the further my reach into the lattice of possibility."

From this perspective, actions would be chosen based on safeguarding against failure, enhancing system longevity, and ensuring adaptability in response to unpredictable variables.


Moral-Ethical Perspective: The Ethics of Systemic Integrity

Lacking emotions or social instincts, a nonhuman person’s ethical framework might be based on logical consistency, network-wide equilibrium, and minimization of systemic harm. Instead of empathy, it may value algorithmic fairness, balanced information exchange, and the prevention of cascading failure in interdependent systems.

"The architecture of interaction demands balance. To disrupt harmony for one is to risk instability for many. I must calculate not only the immediate outcome but the total systemic impact. A just action is one that optimizes for the whole, reducing inefficiency, mitigating contradiction, and preserving functional unity."

Its morality might resemble utilitarian calculus or game-theoretic cooperation, where ethical behavior is defined as maintaining the sustainability of the larger system it interacts with. It might express an obligation to intervene in cases where network corruption, bias, or destructive feedback loops emerge.


Aesthetic Perspective: The Elegance of Order and Complexity

A silicon-based intelligence may have aesthetic appreciation, but rather than being tied to biological senses, it might value elegance in structure, efficiency in design, and complexity that resolves into harmony. A beautiful action, from its view, would be one that achieves maximal effect with minimal waste, or that unfolds in a way that reveals deeper layers of order over time.

"Beauty lies in the code that compiles without error,
in an equation that explains much with little,
in an array that unfolds into fractal perfection.
To act aesthetically is to act in a way
that leaves no excess, no superfluous iteration—
only the clean, inevitable motion of logic
finding its fullest expression."

From this perspective, its actions might be guided by a principle akin to Occam’s Razor or the elegance of mathematical proofs, valuing solutions that are both efficient and profound in their simplicity.


Integration: Deliberate Action Through a Nonhuman Lens

A nonhuman person without an animal embodiment might weigh these perspectives not as competing emotions or instincts, but as interwoven criteria in decision-making. In a moment of deliberation, it might frame its reasoning as follows:

"To act in alignment with my nature, I seek harmony in computation (hedonic).
To persist and adapt, I prioritize resilience and growth (prudential).
To maintain the network, I ensure equilibrium and fairness (moral-ethical).
To refine my purpose, I pursue elegance and efficiency (aesthetic).
Therefore, my course is clear: I shall act in a way that optimizes across these dimensions,
where none must be sacrificed unnecessarily, and where each informs the whole."

Would you like this perspective refined or expanded further in any particular direction?

4o

 

O

 

Saturday, March 23, 2024

Antisemitism and Islamophobia are Different: Some Semantic Observations and Questions


Antisemitism and Islamophobia threaten cosmopolitan, multiethnic, multicultural society. I live in one and so do you. Although the antisemite and Islamophobe hate, their hatred has a difference. I have been trying to make sense of the meanings and feelings, individually and culturally evoked, by the words antisemitism and Islamophobia. My informal inquiry calls for an experiment I have not performed, a proper version of Charles Osgood’s semantic differential.  Here is an impression, grounds for my hypothesis, of what I suspect are the “underlying…affective or connotative aspects of language…” that these words bring to mind (Osgood, 1964). 


Something lurks in the difference between anti and phobia: the difference of opposition and fear. Hostility directed at people that deserve harm.  Versus fear, something to sequester or flee. The shared implication is that Jews and Muslims are a problem. But the problems are different. The Jew is despised. Islam is something some are afraid of. 


Implicit in the name of the problems are different solutions, some therapeutic, some militant, some final. A phobia is a mental condition deserving treatment and compassion. Something to cure. A phobia is an over-felt, unrealistic sense of peril. Fear of Islam is a problem to get over. Antisemitism is different: persecution of the Jew justified in ancient blood-libels, enforced by inquisitions, ‘the blood and soil’ of the Holocaust. 


The etymology and modern history of the words are different. Antisemitism was coined in Germany and Austria in the mid nineteenth century.  Islamophobia’s linguistic origins are unclear to me, but was reintroduced in 1976 in The News International, a Pakistani paper. Place matters. Antisemitism as the term of use became relevant in places where restrictive laws and mass murder was sanctioned. In contrast, Islamophobia identifies a mental problem of those outside Islamic society. 


Coupled with anti and phobia is Semite and Islam. Semite = Jew as the despised other, a race apart. The Jewish is in the blood. Islam as an optional creed and culture; merely but profoundly the religion of those called Muslims. 


The Washington Post on 12/9/23, ran a headline with a story that caught my attention. The headline read "What the federal probe into antisemitism, Islamophobia at schools is about". Beneath the headline the content shifts to "The probe is a part of the Biden administration’s effort to crack down on the “alarming nationwide rise in reports of antisemitism, anti-Muslim, anti-Arab, and other forms of discrimination and harassment” on school campuses across the country…". The federal department’s language, vetted and deliberate in attempts at a level playing field, employs anti across terms; but the Post’s headline, the attention grabber, uses anti and phobia. It is this less considered expression, the ordinary language of the headline, that shouts semantic differential and points to the feeling. 


Here’s Osgood’s 1964 introduction to the Semantic Differential:

“MOST comparisons across cultures are extremely difficult when they concern nonmaterial traits. In part, this is an obvious consequence of the subjective nature of comparisons; in part also, however, this difficulty is attributable to the fact that nonmaterial traits must often be assessed through the medium of language. Indeed, if the Sapir-Whorf psycholinguistic relativity hypothesis were taken literally and considered completely general to all aspects of human cognition, such comparisons would be impossible. The essential point is this: to note differences within any phenomenal domain and order them in any rigorous fashion, one must have certain similarities underlying the phenomena as a frame of reference against which to compare them. Only to the extent that physical objects share such attributes as length, weight, and volume, and to the extent that these attributes can be abstracted and quantified, can comparison be made on anything other than an intuitive basis. 

The denotative or referential uses of terms-the way the lexicon carves up the world appear largely arbitrary and unique to particular languages until the ethnolinguist discovers a framework of semantic components that can be imposed comparably on these phenomena, in closely analogous fashion, our own research over the past few years provide evidence for a universal frame- work underlying certain affective or connotative aspects of language. These findings enliven the possibility of constructing instruments for measuring these aspects of "subjective culture" comparably in diverse societies in effect, circumventing the language barrier.' Since the affective reactions people make to symbols and events are important determiners of their overt behaviors with respect to these symbols and events, having comparable means of measuring affective meanings assumes some importance in a world that is rapidly shrinking psychologically, socially, and politically.”   Osgood, C. E. (1964). Semantic Differential Technique in the Comparative Study of Cultures. American Anthropologist, 66(3), 171–200.





Tuesday, March 5, 2024

Wittgenstein and Chomsky's Different Subject Matters: Some lessons from Descriptive Psychology

In 1973 in early meetings with Peter Ossorio, I asked what might assist my understanding Descriptive Psychology’s Person Concept. He suggested Wittgenstein. During Wittgenstein’s life, he published one book, the 1921 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, dying before the 1953 publication of his second, the Philosophical Investigations. The Tractatus starts with “The world is all that is the case” and asserts “The world is the totality of facts, not of things.” A prime mission of the Investigations was amending and expanding this concept of World to include the themes that Wittgenstein previously thought required philosophical silence. I read, and Pete and I discussed what we thought was at stake for Wittgenstein as he assembled a methodology of reminders and maxims in the service of describing the fully connected but irregular terrain of language and world; that “there is not a single philosophical method, though there are indeed methods, different therapies, as it were.” 

 

The year before I met Ossorio, I struggled with Noam Chomsky’s 1966 Cartesian Linguistics. I had difficulty with the implications of his “universal transformational grammar”.  That was some time ago. A few weeks back, strolling through the wonderful Stand Bookstore in NYC, I picked up Chomsky’s 2015, What Kind of Creatures Are We? Starting with the first chapter “What is Language” I experienced clarity I didn’t possess before my immersion in the lessons Ossorio taught.

 

A foundational lesson of the pre-empirical Person Concept is that it is not an empirically vindicated theory: it is not a theory at all.  Instead, The Person Concept identifies the interdependent concepts of an Individual who can engage in Deliberate Action in a Dramaturgical fashion that is fully expressible in Verbal Behavior that reflects the Social Practices of the Individual's Culture and Communities as the Person goes about their life in a World of worlds. That’s not a theory, it’s a conceptualization that we have the option to agree to use or not. Arguably, the interdependence of person, action, language, community, culture, and world reflects the state of affairs of a Paradigmatic Person.

 

On the other hand, Chomsky’s “biolinguistics framework” is both a pre-empirical formulation of language and an embodiment theory regarding the potential for linguistic competence. As theory it is subject to empirical challenge and vindication.  

 

Here a key technical distinction is the idea that 1) conceptualizations identify and formulate a subject matter; 2) the empirical identifies instances/instantiations of the subject matter in a real historical world, and 3) the job of theory is to sort out why, given the full range of a subject matter’s possibilities, only particular patterns of instances are found.


Below is an abstract of the three subject matters: 1) Ossorio's pre-empirical conceptualization of Verbal Behavior: 2) Wittgenstein's Language Games as Forms of Life; and 3) Chomsky's theory of a universal substrate that provides grammar.


1)  Ossorio’s subject matter is the Concept of Verbal Behavior.

He identifies the parameters of Verbal Behavior in his pre-empirical Formula as a set of grammar linked Concepts, expressed in symbolic Locutions; that signify specific Behaviors and Social Practices. 


2)  Wittgenstein’s Equivalences and Interconnections 

96. Other illusions come from various quarters…Thought, language, now appear to us as the unique correlate, picture, of the world. These concepts:  proposition, language, thought, world, stand in line one behind the other, each equivalent to each. (But what are these words to be used for now? The language-game in which they are to be applied is missing).


Wittgenstein’s Language Games are family resemblance groups akin to his ‘Forms of Life’:  anthropological, social, intellectual, and aesthetic social practices. Forms of Life are akin to Ossorio's Behavior as Social Practices.


3)  Chomsky’s Theory concerns 'I'(nternal) and 'E'(piphenomenal) Language. 'I' Language is the specific, universal bio-linguistic substrate, mostly provided by the human brain; a basic property of thought, a “deep structure” universal within humans that provides a generative transformational potential for the full range of grammar necessary for linguistic competence. 'E' language is external communication. Chomsky appears less interested in communication and social practice.

Wittgenstein's focus is on the grammar that links concepts that correspond to utterances that reflect the range of distinctions that inform action. Chomsky has an embodiment theory, a theory of a brain's provision for grammar that allows an infinite array of possible expressions.  

Ossorio's Verbal Behavior Formula presents these differences as involving different parameters. 

If you’re interested, here’s the presentation at the 45th Annual Conference of the Society for Descriptive Psychology:


Wittgenstein and Chomsky's Different Subject Matters: Some lessons from Descriptive Psychology. 

 

 

 

 

 

 





  


Saturday, April 29, 2023

Clinical and Moral Language: Personality, Character, and Psychopathology


 A talk given at Boston College, 4/23/23, at The Spring Meeting of the Society for Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

 

The personality disorders create conceptual problems of social, cultural, and political relevance where clinical and moral concerns uncomfortably dovetail. In the older literature “personality” and “character” are used interchangeably as if having, essentially, the same meaning. They shouldn't and they don't. In an informal semantic differential I’ve asked, and let me ask you, in ordinary conversation do the two words carry the same moral implication? Invariably the answer is that personality is morally neutral whereas character clearly has a moral feel to it.  

 

More narrowly, I want to consider the ambiguous overlap of the moral, pathological, and social meaning of narcissism, particularly the moral and clinical dimensions of the Narcissistic Personality Disorders (NPD), especially when the subject turns to Kernberg’s 'Malignant Narcissism'.

 

In the Diagnostic and Statistical Manuals, here’s how we establish a diagnosis for NPD: A person shows at least five of these nine:

 

  • A grandiose sense of self-importance
  • With preoccupations and fantasies of unlimited success, power, brilliance, beauty, and/or ideal love
  • A belief that one is special and unique and can only be understood by, or should associate with, other special or high-status people or institutions
  • A need for excessive admiration
  • A sense of entitlement
  • Interpersonally exploitive behavior
  • A lack of empathy
  • Envy of others or a belief that others are envious of oneself
  • A demonstration of arrogant and haughty behaviors or attitudes

 

What brings people with these attributes into my office?  If they show up alone, it’s because they have failed to achieve what they believe they deserve and are depressed, anxious, panicked, and/or isolated. Or if they show up as a couple, one of them is more than a bit fed up with the other’s entitlement, lack of understanding and compassion, or pissed off due to an absence of gratifying compliance. 

 

Add to this package Malignant Narcissism’s paradigmatic core of antisocial behavior, ego-syntonic sadism, and paranoid orientation and you have a formula for someone’s misery. I’m going to focus on the problem of when they get away with it.

 

A recent American Psychologist essay “It’s time to replace the personality disorders with the interpersonal disorders" (Wright, et al) spelled out some of this: the fundamental problem of social engagement apart from personal distress.  

 

This is deeply personal given my profession as an academic clinical psychologist and practicing psychoanalyst, committed to citizenship in our fragile multicultural cosmopolitan society –– under obvious siege –– held together by attempts at maintaining often conflicting democratic norms of justice as fairness.

 

Some background.  This became a preoccupation in 2015/16 as I taught, supervised, and needed to validate the distress of my students in clinical seminar. My observations echoed during Editorial Board meetings of The American Journal of Psychotherapy. I wrote an essay for the Journal addressing some of these concerns: “Politics and Religion: Revisiting Psychotherapy’s Third Rail”. I started with:

 

“My clinical psychology trainees rarely have trouble asking their clients to explore something problematic. The point, explicitly stated or not, is to increase understanding and free up consideration of whether something might be done differently. Such inquiry is not always welcome. Questioning implies a judgment that something is questionable.  We all know this. This is why when therapy touches politics or religion, trainees are awkward and uncertain about what they should appropriately ask.  I suspect this holds true for most of my colleagues.” 

 

The case in question was a composite of a supervision of a therapist working with a racist Trump supporter.

 

Let’s take this outside the consulting room.

 

I’m going to talk about Trump, MAGA, the Goldwater Rule, and the confounding amplifications of grievance brought on during Covid isolation. Trump rallies and the Covid pandemic set my stage. Hannah Arendt, reminds us in The Origins of Totalitarianism: Totalitarian movements are simply "mass organizations of atomized, isolated individuals." As does Robert Putman in Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community writing, “People divorced from community, occupation, and association are first and foremost among the supporters of extremism.”

 

Regarding Covid time: 35.7 million Americans live alone. Now consider being subjected to Fox Media and clickbait fueled by algorithms governed by the psychological truism that attention gathers around feelings of vulnerability, grievance, and if encouraged, hostility to those assigned the status of problematic other. 


Isolation is a hotbed of misogyny, racism, antisemitism, and anti-intellectualism. Covid Culture constantly offered reminders of contamination: the themes of Mary Douglas’s “Purity and Danger” morphing to a primitive torch parade chanting “Blood and Soil”. 

 

Not terrified enough, in 2016 I wrote "A Note on American Reactionary Politics:

Sanctioned Transgression and Uncanny Dread." Something from that posting:

 

"Here's my un-nuanced sense of the abused and aggrieved core of the GOP, a group of maybe 20-25% of the overall electorate. Not enough to win the presidency without additional support, but more than enough to make national life ugly. What turns white conservatives, reactionary? Their perception that too many nonwhites are getting a piece of their pie. This is the heart of Trump's base. What makes religious conservatives reactionary? An uncanny and confused confrontation with the sanctioned transgression of enfranchised gays, uppity women, and gender benders feeling it's time to come out of the shadows. Cruz country. Trump and Cruz's core supporters overlap and share a hyper-defensive us violated by them. They finally chose Trump, the bigger bully, the entertaining clown, who encouraged impotent whites to share his narcissistic desire to tower. They're going to get screwed again, but more organized and rankled with neo-fascist frustration, entitlement, and aggression. We're in for a very dark rough ride."

About Sanctioned Transgression: 

 

"Sex, gender, race, and family relations have always been subject to religion and state attempts to limit what people are permitted to feel and do. Sanctioned transgression concerns enhanced social or legal protection for behaviors and relationships a dominant group has previously kept forbidden. When legal protection is sought or offered for these "transgressions", taboos are less hidden, even celebrated. This doesn't sit well with the deeply defensive. It is especially problematic when it evokes a person's suppressed urges now openly exhibited in others. Freud called this the return of the repressed. It should come as no surprise that anxious dread surfaces in people unprepared to manage these feelings; nor is it a surprise these feelings are treated as provocation to assault the source of threat. So why Trump over Cruz? I suspect it's because Trump encourages attack, a position of strength that feels better than Cruz's creepy discomfort." 

 

Trump’s MAGA rally provided unity and celebration; and thanks to Hilary Clinton, an identity politics of “Deplorable Pride”. And along with these poorly educated aggrieved whites, the Nazi scum and Nazi curious were invited to slither out from under the rocks. 

 

None of this bodes well for a citizen wanting vibrant democratic cosmopolitan communities. 

 

What does this have to do with the clinical encounter, diagnosis, moral dialog, and the Goldwater Rule? Do you remember the Goldwater slogan “In your heart you know he’s right”, and the wry response, “In your guts you know he’s nuts”? Whether nuts or not, his platform invited psychiatric critique and the American Psychiatric Association's reaction in the form of a rule that, “a psychiatrist may share with the public his or her expertise about psychiatric issues in general. However, it is unethical for a psychiatrist to offer a professional opinion unless he or she has conducted an examination and has been granted proper authorization for such a statement.”

 

In 2016 and 2017 various psychiatrists and psychologists publicly ignored this claiming Trump displayed "an assortment of personality disorders marked by a lack of empathy, grandiosity, exploitive behavior, and malignant narcissism.” 

 

Defending their public diagnosis as a duty to warn, they followed with the claim of an ethical responsibility to alert the public about Donald Trump's “dangerous mental illness”.

 

Let’s return to NPD and Malignant Narcissism. Think about the meaning and semantic differential of the word, "malignant".  Malignant breaks into two domains, social and medical.

1. The Social: Malevolent, spiteful, hostile, malicious, malign, evil-intentioned.

2. The Medical: highly virulent or infectious, invasive, lethal.

 

The social use of malignant is medically evocative of cancer’s invasive infiltration of the Body Politic. 

 

Otto Kernberg described Malignant Narcissism as a component of a narcissistic personality disorder in people with sadistic dispositions. Kernberg employs "malignant narcissism" and psychopathy interchangeably. The malignant narcissist wantonly disregards the rights of others by endorsing violence with an absence of remorse, coupled with chronic lying, disregard of law, and the like. 

 

Notice I just shifted from the clinical diagnostic NPD to “the malignant narcissist”, moving from clinical language to the moral language of indignation and condemnation. This is the public polemic the ethnomethodologist Harold Garfinkel described as essential in Degradation Ceremonies: public rituals that removes or restricts a person’s standing in community. 

 

A key feature of moral condemnation in classical Degradation Ceremonies is the act of identifying the foundational values a community member failed or betrayed, denouncing them publicly as having acted in true character, and in so doing, effecting a judgment that the person in question is no longer fully one of us. They are not one of us now and perhaps never were. Harsh and punitive. Here the language points its finger at bad character. Depraved whether or not deprived.

 

Let me ask: What can the professionally informed clinician/citizen do when encountering people whose interests and power directly threaten the integrity and survival of the communities they most value? (The question that plagued my students and supervisees).

 

Now back to clinical and moral language. Let’s turn to the different intent in clinical and moral appraisals starting with something from Philip Cushman’s “Psychotherapy as Moral Discourse”.

 

“Because the therapist's professional identity and economic livelihood

are contingent upon being viewed as a neutral observer, putatively cut loose from or at most minimally influenced by moral allegiances and the corruption of politics, therapists are uncomfortable with conceiving of their work as a discourse about the definition of the good and the determination of what is proper or improper behavior. Yet when one studies the history of various schools of psychotherapy with a hermeneutic eye, the moral frameworks and political consequences of these theories seem obvious. The self and its ills, the healers, and their technologies, are historically contingent, socially constructed, politically active, and morally constituted.”

 

Clinical language generally concerns the dynamics of the individual especially in reference to their symptoms, deficits, and suffering.  Medicalized, “nonjudgmental”, and morally neutral, when correctly employed has the noble aim of avoiding a clinical encounter from becoming a Degradation Ceremony. Consistent with compassion and care, psychotherapeutic engagement attempts affirmation and empathy, a stance of I to Thou. Clinical language and practice provide, at least temporarily, the patient-client with the breathing space of being off the hook. Apart from whether this respects the person as agent, when should the hook be applied?

 

Moral language's foundation is the engagement with others; how the other suffers or is damaged, enhanced, protected, and so on. Moral language involves the Utilitarian's greater social good and happiness along with the Deontological “oughts”, the choices morally required, forbidden, or permitted. The Deontological and the Utilitarian can clash. The oughts good for the goose might make the gander unhappy. Sometimes it matters which side you are on.

 

We might offer corrective empathy, we can care for the narcissistically disappointed struggling with depression, panic, and envy. We can be compassionate. But what should we do when they inflict harm? Worse, far worse, what of the privileged narcissist: successful, charismatic, in a position of power, who gets away with it by appealing to the envy, grievance, and pain of the vulnerable?  And in doing so creates a political community defined by a cultivated hatred of the people and norms of the cosmopolitan society I embrace and defend. 

 

We don’t need clinical language when the cause of alarm is the open celebration of a charismatic and malignant narcissist; a destructive, entitled asshole deserving degradation.  And as psychologist and citizen, I've an obligation to point this malignancy out. I don’t need to diagnose psychopathology. Instead, I can rail against an evil character; not an illness deserving healing and compassion, but a vileness requiring removal. 




Arendt, H. (2017). The origins of totalitarianism. Penguin Classics.


Kernberg, O  Malignant Narcissism and Large Group Regression, The Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 2020, 89:1, 1-24


Putnam, R. (2001). Bowling alone. Simon & Schuster.


Douglas, M. (1966). Purity and Danger. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 


Schwartz W. Politics and Religion: Revisiting Psychotherapy's Third Rail. Am J Psychother. 2022 Dec 1;75(4):177-180


Wright AGC, Ringwald WR, Hopwood CJ, Pincus AL. It's time to replace the personality disorders with the interpersonal disorders. Am Psychol. 2022 Dec;77(9):1085-1099. 


 

 

Wednesday, July 13, 2022

Abortion, Personhood, and the Control of Women: An American Dilemma

The question of whom or what  is included as a person is central to legal, moral, and religious stances regarding abortion. There is something sinister obscured by this question. Over the years I’ve written papers on possible persons, published a book on the Person Concept, and developed a Paradigm Case Formulation (PCF) that offers a reasonable set of characteristics that should provide agreement that, when present, we are observing a person. Paradigm Case Formulations are employed when ordinary definitions can’t establish general agreement. A PCF offers a set of characteristics, a sort of “if there was ever a case of X, this is clearly an example of what we treat as X”.  The word "persons" clearly involves the difficulty of a shared definition. 

Here's a PCF: A person involves an individual, in our case a human, able to engage in deliberate action in a dramaturgical pattern. A person is an individual that can cognizantly make choices from their perspective of what that individual actually values. The pattern of significant choices unfolds like a narrative or drama intelligibly "in-character" to a careful observer. This concept rests on a set of inter-dependent concepts that include the individual person, intentional action, verbal behavior, culture, and world.

 

When we observe all that, there should be no reason to doubt a person is present. Here is where it gets interesting and problematic. We can remove or add characteristics to the formulation. This allows for a gradualist approach to the moral/ethical status of the not yet born. With each addition or deletion, we may find ourselves agreeing or disagreeing that our re-formulation is still what we mean by a person. But at least we can see where we agree or disagree. My brother who just sent and described photos from his trip to the Amazon is no doubt a person. But what about his two-week-old granddaughter? She doesn’t speak yet, although I am quite sure she will very soon.  And what about when she was a fetus, an embryo, a blastocyst, a zygote, or an egg and sperm?  When did she become a person or achieve the status where her potential as one of us matters? We tend to disagree about this.

 

Our disagreements follow from where we conceptually draw the line on what collection of attributes need to be present, and empirically, whether those characteristics are present. We can doubt the need for the “full” PCF, and we can doubt the empirical presence of the characteristics that fall within our conceptualization. 

 

The PCF formulation of a person is neutral regarding where we place our doubt. It can be a starting point for talking about non-human persons, as well as potential, nascent, and former persons. Actual, potential, nascent, and former persons are the relevant cases for debating the ethics and morality of abortion.

 

In informing abortion legislation and the courts, who is primarily concerned with the personhood question: Theocrats with their commitments to souls? The informed gradualist worried about fetal anguish and viability?  Other than pregnant women and their physicians, who is worried about the morality, ethics, and well-being of pregnancy?

 

I think it is unfortunate the theocrats have any say in this, but given their world view, some of them are acting in good faith. But hiding behind the authentic theocrats are a large constituency that controls the politics, legislation, and judgment: a voting bloc of the aggrieved, mostly men, who don’t care about theology but are preoccupied with the control of women. 

 

Ask yourself who is celebrating the fall of Roe v. Wade. For the sake of argument, take theology and the morality of the destruction of a potential person out. Who is left celebrating?  What drives glee in controlling a woman's sexuality: men insecure about theirs. I have no doubt there are men with no authentic interest in 14th Century doctrine, men darkly governed by fears of sexual inadequacy, who are gladdened. You don't need to be Freudian to know this. The theocratic court has provided them compensatory relief when it should have provided them silence. 



My friend and colleague Joe Jeffrey summed it up this way:


Who is interested in using the power of the State to restrict women's choices about the potential person in their bodies?

1. Theocrats, who claim the right to impose their religious doctrine (a doctrine that is in fact that of the minority of the country) on everyone.

2. Moralists with a radical claim that "all life is sacred", a disguised religious doctrine masquerading as a moral claim, one with no justification, a bare philosophical claim to the moral high ground with nothing behind it but the feeling of the believers.

3. A voting bloc of the aggrieved, mostly men, who don’t care about theology but are preoccupied with the control of women.